« Comme la mode fait l'agrément, aussi fait-elle la justice. La justice
change selon les pays. Ce qui est juste sur le bord d'un fleuve est injuste
de l'autre côté; et cette instabilité est encore un effet de la faiblesse
humaine, car il fallait que la justice fût unie à la force pour conserver la
paix, qui est le souverain bien. [...] La justice n'a donc été chez les
différentes nations que l'expression de la volonté du plus fort. Ainsi il ne
faut pas dire au peuple que ses lois sont injustes; car il est quelquefois
nécessaire de le tromper; il ne faut pas même lui dire qu'il doit obéir aux
lois parce qu'elles sont justes; il n'aurait qu'à vouloir les examiner: il
faut lui dire qu'il doit leur obéir parce qu'elles sont établies, car il faut
surtout éviter les séditions. »
1
Blaise Pascal, Pensées 309
Chapter 1
Classical and modern theory of just war and jus ad bellum
The perpetual genesis of the idea of „just‟ and „justice‟
Introduction
To understand when a conflict is considered legitimate today and to comprehend
the bases that determine NATO‟s decision-making on the lawfulness of an
intervention, it is necessary to introduce a preliminary historical remark on the
topic, which has constituted the focal point of the discipline of “just war”.
The main overarching idea of the present chapter is that affirming that an action or
a phenomenon is just implies stating our own ideas about the world but also
reveals those norms and values that we have been absorbing from the society.
Thus, the evaluation of the lawfulness of an armed intervention encapsulates
social, societal, sometimes even geographical and generational significances.
1
Translation of the author of the present work: “As customs determine what is agreeable, also
does it determine justice. Justice changes from country to country. What is just on one bank of a
river is unjust on the other bank. It is this instability that is further effect of human weakness, since
it would be necessary to combine justice and strength to consolidate peace, which is the supreme
good. Therefore justice has not been anything but the expression of the will of the strongest in the
different nations. So, one cannot tell people that their laws are unjust because sometimes it is
necessary to break transgress them. Similarly, one cannot tell them to break laws since laws are
just. There will not be any much choice but to examine them. It is necessary to tell people to obey
since laws are established and, most of all, because we must avoid seditions.”
1
By providing an excursus on the evolution of the theory of just war, this chapter
will show how the concept has developed according to the legal and institutional
framework in which it has been embedded and how it has evolved around three
main motifs: religion, politics and morality.
The first section will introduce the theory of just war and will refer to the first
scholars interpreting it, from Plato to Thucydides going through Aristotle. The
remark on the Hellenic time is necessary to introduce the naissance of the idea of
justice within a variegated conjunction of myths and polytheist cults.
The following paragraph will devote its attention to the evolution of the discipline
within the religious motif. It will focus indeed on the Roman tradition both
relevant for Augustine of Hippo‟s contribution – for many the founding father of
the concept of „just war‟ – but also for the primarily attempt of the Roman legal
system of legislating conflicts. Thus, the analysis of the religious justification of
conflict will proceed with the other two main monotheistic religions: Judaism and
Islam.
The next section will synopsize the „political‟ tradition of legitimizing conflicts. It
will pick up the thread of the narrative initiated by Thucydides and will present
Machiavelli‟s raison d‟état, which epitomizes the significance of just war theory
within the mere context of state actors. Within the political justification of war
falls as well the more modern contribution provided by Hugo Grotius and the sets
for the international order established by the Peace of Westphalia.
As the new legal system engendered by these two latter contributions started to
take a concrete form, international institutions have entered the game with the
attempt of institutionalizing, regulating and avoiding conflicts. However, such
institutions have introduced a third factor to the tradition of just war: the moral
universal category. As a matter of facts, within the context of a more
institutionalized system, framed within concrete legal constraints, the League of
Nations has been presenting itself as the champion of world peace, rather as a
military organization that aimed to guarantee the security of only certain states.
The League of Nations eventually paved the way to our coeval institutions, as the
United Nations, an organization that can be located in both political and moral
categories, albeit the latter certainly prevails. What about NATO, the cardinal
point of the present thesis? As it will fully illustrated in Chapters 2, the Treaty of
2
the Alliance presents mainly political justifications although Chapter 3 will argue
that the moral pretext is becoming more and more recurrent.
1.1 Defining “just war”
The reasons behind an armed intervention have historically been determined by
what the actor perpetrating the hostilities has considered just and they have been
interpreted by the international community in which it is embedded according to
the legal system in force. This implies that the notions of justice and the
justification of a conflict have gone through an extensive evolution over centuries,
and thus a particular foreign policy might have been considered reasonable and
permissible at Thucydides‟ time, while it might be seen illegal and unacceptable
today. Such considerations on the validity of an armed intervention do not take
place only at the eyes of the single citizens or of single states, but also in the
presence of the international community, conceived as a unitary legitimating
actor.
The debate presented in the present chapter will be modelled on two main
concepts: justification - or legitimization - and the connotation just - or necessary.
It is not by chance that the two concepts that the words „justification‟ (possibly
connected to perceptions and opinions or, in other words, what can be done) and
„justice‟ (more determined and factual, what has to be done and commonly
associated with an objective perspective), for how conceptually different, found
origin in the same etymologic root.
Finally, the connotation of „justice‟ and „justification‟ (of a war) have been
evolving over time and for centuries both single nations and the international
society have tried to reach agreements in order to regulate and prevent wars, to
understand when an intervention can be waged (according what is perceived to be
just in that particular moment of time) and when it should be conducted (in
accordance to what the predominant judicial system believes to be justifiable).
1.2. The incipience of the discipline in Greek tradition
Before starting the digression on the mere concept of just war, it seems
appropriate to introduce a short remark on the concept of justice introduced in the
3
Western tradition by Plato, reshaped by Aristotle and eventually associated by
Thucydides with the necessity of waging a conflict. Indeed, only by defining first
the meaning of that „jus‟ contained in the expressions ius ad bellum (“the right to
wage a war”) and ius in bello (“war waged justly”) it will be possible to fully
understand the significance of such expressions and the evolution that their
connotations have experienced over time.
As mentioned above, Plato was a pioneer in introducing dissertations on the idea
of justice. In the Republic, the Greek sage (428 BC – 348 BC) exposed one of the
most exhaustive studies on what is and has to be just
2
. A just man – he writes –
will never be able to harm another one
3
. Moreover, Plato inaugurates Book VIII
of his oeuvre with Socrates‟ elucidation on the conduction of a war: its pursuits
must be shared and unambiguous, the king has to have full responsible leadership
and its limitations and boundaries need to be clear as well. As it will be shown
during the redaction of the present thesis, are these very characteristics that set the
bases for the discipline of just war theory.
The second early contribution to such branch of learning was provided by one of
Plato‟s disciples, Aristotle (384 BC – 322 BC). In Aristotle‟s conception, the
bellum iustum was intended as a way of regulating relations among states. For the
peripatetic scholar a war is legitimate whenever three conditions – or dìkaios
pòlemos - are met: as a self-defensive measure against subjugation; as a way of
establishing a hegemonic rule for the interest and benefit of the ones who are
subdued; and in order to enslave those who deserve to be enslaved
45
.
As a final remark on the Greek tradition, it is necessary to point out that also in
the Peloponnesian War are presented explicit references to the right to wage a
war. In fact, in the infamous Melian Dialogue
6
, Thucydides (460 BC – 395 BC)
encapsulates some of the most relevant concepts that centuries later would be
2
With the purpose of engendering in the reader a profound reasoning on the notion of justice, the
author mounts a dialectic disputes between Thrasymachus – who believes that justice is “what is
advantageous to the stronger, while injustice is to one's own profit and advantage"
2
– and Socrates
who sustain the opposite. The anecdote of Gyges aims as well to amplify the dialectic debate on
justice: in Glaucon‟s speech Plato concentrates the idea that injustice and impunity are strictly
connected – an idea that will come particularly handy in the following sections.
3
Plato, (2004), Republic, Indianapolis, Hackett Publishing Company, p. 12.
4
Aristotle, (reprint: 2006) Politics. Teddington. The Echo Library. 7,1333 b 37- 1334 a 10.
5
A fundamental bibliographic reference on the topic is represented by the following work:
Clavadetscher-Thürlemann S., Pòlemos dìkaios und „bellum iustum‟. Versuch einer
Ideengeschichte, Zürich, 1986
6
The event is part of the Peloponnesian wars and date back to 416 BC, when the King of Sparta,
Archidamus, invades the Athenian territory. Original source: Thucydides V 84 114.
4
identified as part of the Realist School of International Relations. The motifs
presented with the dialogue are abundant: from the legitimation of war as self-
defense (what it has been identified previously as the political justification) to the
perpetual peace; from amorality within politics (again, the political category), to
the relation between ethics and might; from the dissertation on the connotations
on justice (which for the Athenians it is a synonym of the capacity to compel,
while for the Malians it does not), to the connection between power and justice.
What it is possible to infer from such Dialogue is that for the Greek military
general and historian, war is an essential situation that emerges whenever a
political actor attempts to impose its hegemony on a second and weaker party
7
.
Legitimized by the very nature of the actors, war according to Thucydides could
be either defensive or aggressive, but what was sure to the scholar was that it rose
as a consequence of the imbalance of power:
“[…] the strong do what they can and the weak suffer what they must”
8
1.3 Just war in the Roman tradition
Within the ancient Roman tradition we recognize the presence of a peculiar
category in which the legitimation of a conflict falls: the religious-political one.
As a matter of facts, it is interesting to underline how according to one of the most
representative scholar of that time, Cicero, it was a conjunction of mystic and
defensive arguments that allowed the declaration of a war
For Cicero indeed no justification could sustain the decision of initiating a conflict
if not the need of “repelling enemies”
9
with the ultimate aim of establishing
“peace unharmed”
10
. However, he sustained that “legalistic rituals” were the
requisite for legitimization
11
and such rituals represents a novelty introduced by
introduced by the Romans with regards to the discipline of bellum iustum and it
7
He indeed wrote: “The truest cause [of the war] is obscured by speech. I think that Athenians, by
becoming great, inspired fear among the Lacedaemonians, making the war necessary.”
Thucydides, The Peloponnesian Wars, I.72.
8
Ibid, V, 17.
9
Cicero De Officiis I, 11. In Regan R. J. Just war: principles and cases.1996, Washington DC, The
Catholic University Press, p. 16
10
Ibid.
11
Eilers C. Diplomats and diplomacy in the Roman world. 2009. Danvers, MA. Koninklijke Brill,
p. 19.
5